Elsevier

Acta Astronautica

Volume 137, August 2017, Pages 450-460
Acta Astronautica

Myth-free space advocacy part I—The myth of innate exploratory and migratory urges

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.actaastro.2017.05.002Get rights and content

Highlights

  • Advocates for a more reasoned and evidence-based approach to space advocacy.
  • Uses historical evidence to assess whether human cultures are exploratory by nature.
  • Uses genetic evidence to assess whether humans have a genetic urge to explore.

Abstract

This paper discusses the “myth” that we have an innate drive to explore or to migrate into space. Three interpretations of the claim are considered. According to the “mystical interpretation,” it is part of our “destiny” as humans to explore and migrate into space. Such a claim has no rational basis and should play no role in rationally- or evidence-based space advocacy. According to the “cultural interpretation,” exploration and migration are essential features of human culture and society. These are not universal features because there are cultures and societies that have not encouraged exploration and migration. Moreover, the cultures that have explored have seldom conducted exploration for its own sake. According to the “biological interpretation” there is a psychological or genetic basis for exploration or migration. While there is limited genetic evidence for such a claim, that evidence suggests that genes associated with exploratory behavior were selected for subsequent to migration, making it unlikely that these genes played a role in causing migration. In none of these senses is it clearly true that we have an innate drive to explore or migrate into space; and even if we did it would be fallacious to argue that the existence of such a drive justified spaceflight activities.

Introduction

This paper is the first in a series on unjustified assumptions that underlie a wide array of arguments commonly raised in the space advocacy literature, both academic and popular. In the sequels I plan to discuss the “myth” that spaceflight spending has a clear causal impact on STEM education and scientific literacy, as well as the “myth” that settling the space frontier is necessary for avoiding societal stagnation. Here, however, I shall focus on the “myth” that, as humans, we have an innate drive to explore which motivates and justifies our exploration of and migration into space.
The idea that we have an innate drive, tendency, or compulsion to explore or migrate is very much equivocal in the space advocacy literature. It is helpful to distinguish between three broad ways of interpreting claims about our purported exploratory and migratory tendencies—a mystical interpretation; a cultural interpretation; and a biological interpretation.
  • 1.
    According to the mystical interpretation, our innate drive to explore or migrate is explained as a spiritual feature of our humanity—that it is, for instance, our destiny to explore and colonize space.
  • 2.
    According to the cultural interpretation, our innate drive to explore or migrate is identified, via historical or anthropological means, as an essential feature of human cultures and societies.
  • 3.
    According to the biological interpretation, our innate drive to explore or migrate is described as a crucial feature of what it is to be a human being in a physical or behavioral sense, for instance as a claim about our psychology or our genetics.
No matter which interpretation is proferred, space advocates have generally presumed the truth of the claim that we have an innate drive to explore or migrate. That is, space advocates have not taken it upon themselves to collect and assess the kind of evidence that would be needed to confirm claims about, e.g., our cultural or genetic heritage. This unveils belief in our innate drive to explore or migrate as largely a matter of faith, rather than a product of good reasoning.
There is consequently a need to consider whether there is good evidence for either of the interpretations of the claim that we have an innate drive to explore or migrate. Moreover, supposing there is compelling evidence for one or more of the interpretations, we must determine what justification the claim actually provides for the exploration or colonization of space. It is important to stress that these are distinct tasks—if it is indeed true that we have an innate drive to explore or migrate, it does not immediately follow that we ought to explore or colonize space or that it would be a good thing to do so. To insist otherwise would be to commit an instance of the naturalistic fallacy.
As I argue in §2, the mystical interpretation is deeply problematic. Claims about, e.g., human destiny or spirit, have no place in serious, rational, discussion about the justification for space exploration. As I discuss in §3, the evidence for the cultural interpretation is equivocal at best. Existing and historical societies differ vastly with respect to their exploratory and migratory tendencies and ambitions. Moreover, the claim that certain societies are exploratory by nature belies the fact that exploration, in any sense relevant to space exploration, is principally the result of decisions made in specific historical contexts.
The biological interpretation requires a more careful assessment. As I relay in §4, significant psychological and genetic research has been conducted on, e.g., curiosity, novelty seeking, exploration, and migration. The psychological evidence suggests that curiosity is a pervasive human characteristic, but that its focus is far from univocal. There is no evidence demonstrating that, e.g., being curious about “what is over the horizon” is widely shared. From a genetic perspective, certain alleles of the dopamine D4 receptor gene (DRD4) have been shown, albeit tenuously, to be associated with novelty seeking and exploratory behavior. Note that here ‘exploratory behavior’ does not refer exclusively to, e.g., migratory behavior, but to information seeking in a more general sense (e.g. it includes how an infant might “explore” visually a new toy). Nevertheless a correlation has been identified between increased incidence of certain DRD4 polymorphisms and migratory distance from east Africa. To the extent causation can be assigned, the evidence supports a “selection” hypothesis—that these genes were selected for subsequent to prehistoric migration, rather than a “wanderlust” hypothesis according to which these genes impelled migration. The likely explanation for this is that traits associated with novelty seeking DRD4 polymorphisms were probably adaptive for individuals placed in novel environments due to migration.
After responding to two objections in §5 I conclude the paper in §6 by offering a general assessment of the argument that we ought to explore or migrate into space because it is in our nature. My contention is that according to all three interpretations the argument rests on shaky evidential grounds. I find it disconcerting that, concerning an endeavor that is as highly scientifically and technologically oriented as space exploration, many persist in presenting arguments with such a tenebrous connection to reality. And, lack of evidence aside, each interpretation falls victim to the naturalistic fallacy—simply because we may have an innate urge to explore or migrate into space does not serve to ethically justify such exploration or migration. The ethical force of any such justification would have to come instead from showing why, e.g., satisfying these urges would produce good consequences.
Lest the reader think that I am skeptical simpliciter of space exploration, let me clarify that I ardently support space exploration1 and that my quibble here is only with some poorly-substantiated—but ubiquitous—space advocacy rhetoric. Thus I should in no way be interpreted as promoting skepticism about the ultimate value of space exploration. My aim is only to inspire more careful and open thinking about spaceflight rationales.
Before beginning in earnest it should be helpful to draw a further distinction between essential and accidental characterizations of behavior, including exploratory and migratory behavior. Briefly, an accidental behavior would be one that an agent simply happens to engage in, but one that the individual could have easily avoided performing, had their circumstances been different. Meanwhile, an essential behavior would be one that an individual is prone to engage in, for instance, out of habit or compulsion.2 To start with an analogy, as someone who has once changed the brakes on my car, I am a “mechanic” in an accidental sense. That is, I have at least once performed some kind of activity that loosely falls under the purview of automobile repair. However, that single act of brake replacement was hardly inevitable given my personality and past experiences, and neither was it predictive regarding my subsequent actions (as I have not in the dozen years since then engaged in any other form of automobile repair beyond, e.g., filling tires, replenishing wiper fluid, etc.). Thus I am not a mechanic in anything like an essential sense, which would require me to be someone for whom there is evidence that suggests unequivocally that they seek out or are prone to engage in further acts of automobile repair. Similarly, we could say of an individual (or culture or species) that has performed at least one act of exploration that they are an exploring individual. But the mere fact of having carried out at least one act of exploration would only establish that this was an exploring individual in an accidental sense. However, to be an exploring individual (or culture or species) in an essential sense would require evidence that this individual explores out of, e.g., habit or innate compulsion.
The accidental/essential distinction is important for evaluating spaceflight rationales which are based on the assumption that humans are explorers by nature. If the evidence only supports the claim that humans are explorers accidentally, then that evidence provides no basis for predicting or justifying future exploratory endeavors. However, I do not take space advocates to be promulgating the idea that we are explorers (according to either the mystical, cultural, or biological interpretations) merely accidentally but that our exploring is essential behavior. For instance, in describing the exploration of space as a component of human destiny, one hardly means that someday humans might simply happen to explore space (or might have to because of external circumstances, such as resource depletion on Earth), but instead that such exploration is inevitable simply because we are humans. So in what follows, the important question is not whether there are or have been individuals or cultures that merely have explored, but instead whether, as a norm, individuals and cultures have some kind of innate compulsion to explore.

Section snippets

The mystical interpretation

According to the mystical interpretation, humans are explorers essentially in the sense that it is the destiny—the fate—of humanity to explore and migrate into space. Examples of the mystical interpretation include the following passage from Buzz Aldrin and Wyn Wachhorst:
Like the sailing ships that incarnated the aura of the Renaissance, or the great steam locomotives that embodied the building of America, the Apollo rocket is an emblem of the human spirit. Apollo was inevitable from the first

The cultural interpretation

If the mystical interpretation is both intrinsically and extrinsically problematic—because it is both equivocal and counterproductive—then might the cultural interpretation fare better? According to this interpretation, our status as essential explorers or migrators is identified as a property of human cultures or societies, which presumably can be tested against evidence provided to us by, e.g. historians and anthropologists.5

The biological interpretation

According to the biological interpretation, a tendency to explore or migrate is an essential behavioral trait that is common to all humans—or is at least one that comes naturally to many of us. More fully, a tendency to explore or migrate is the product of our evolution, and thus when we explore and migrate we are simply behaving in a way dictated by millions of years of natural selection. Examples of the biological interpretation in the space advocacy literature can be found in the writings of

Objections

Here I would like to discuss two objections that might be raised against my criticism of various attempts to justify spaceflight by means of our purported essential exploratory tendencies. One relates to a distinction between human behavior over the short term versus human behavior on a species scale; and a second relates to the role of mythical motivations in human societies.16
The first objection is that all I have established is a very

Conclusion

Neither the mystical, cultural, nor biological interpretation of our innate drive to explore fares well as a premise for the conclusion that we ought to explore or colonize space. Proponents of these interpretations have a worryingly dogmatic view of space exploration—one that seems based more on faith and wishful thinking than on empirically verifiable or rationally compelling evidence. Proponents of the mystical interpretation promulgate an unfalsifiable claim—that we have a destiny, and that

Funding sources

This research did not receive any specific grant from funding agencies in the public, commercial, or not-for-profit sectors.

Acknowledgments

Thanks to Susan Castro, Luke Matthews, Linda Billings, and Cameron Smith for discussion and comments.
James S.J. Schwartz (Ph.D.) teaches philosophy at Wichita State University. His areas of research include the ethics and philosophy of space exploration and policy; environmental ethics; and philosophy of mathematics. He is editor (with Tony Milligan) of The Ethics of Space Exploration (New York: Springer, 2016). His publications have appeared in Space Policy, Advances in Space Research, Environmental Ethics, Ethics & the Environment, Philosophia Mathematica, and in several volumes of

References (46)

  • E. Wang et al.

    The genetic architecture of selection at the human dopamine receptor d4 (drd4) gene locus

    Am. J. Hum. Genet.

    (2004)
  • E. Gören

    The biogeographic origins of novelty-seeking traits

    Evol. Hum. Behav.

    (2016)
  • R. Slobodian

    Selling space colonization and immortality: a psychosocial, anthropological critique of the rush to colonize mars

    Acta Astronaut.

    (2015)
  • B. Aldrin et al.

    The urge to explore

    Mech. Eng.

    (2004)
  • P. Lin

    Look before taking another leap for mankind—ethical and social considerations in rebuilding society in space

    Astropolitics

    (2006)
  • J. Dator

    Social Foundations of Human Space Exploration

    (2012)
  • S. Pyne

    The third great age of discovery

  • C. Smith et al.

    Emigrating beyond Earth: Human Adaptation and Space Colonization

    (2012)
  • P. Limerick

    Imagined frontiers: westward expansion and the future of the space program

  • C. Sagan

    Cosmos

    (2013)
  • I. Crawford

    Towards an integrated scientific and social case for human space exploration

    Earth Moon Planets

    (2005)
  • P. Clancy et al.

    Looking for Life: Searching the Solar System

    (2005)
  • J. Schwartz et al.

    Some ethical constraints on near-earth resource exploitation

  • Cited by (9)

    • Myth-free space advocacy part III: The myth of educational inspiration

      2018, Space Policy
      Citation Excerpt :

      This paper is the third in a series on unsubstantiated beliefs that pervade the space advocacy literature and rhetoric, both academic and popular. In Part I [25], I criticized the myth that as humans we have some kind of innate drive or compulsion to explore. In Part II [26], I criticized the myth that settling the space “frontier” is necessary for avoiding societal stagnation.

    • What do we need to ask before settling space?

      2021, JBIS Journal of the British Interplanetary Society
    • The Value of Science in Space Exploration

      2020, Value of Science in Space Exploration
    • Humans Should Not Colonize Mars

      2017, Journal of the American Philosophical Association
    View all citing articles on Scopus
    James S.J. Schwartz (Ph.D.) teaches philosophy at Wichita State University. His areas of research include the ethics and philosophy of space exploration and policy; environmental ethics; and philosophy of mathematics. He is editor (with Tony Milligan) of The Ethics of Space Exploration (New York: Springer, 2016). His publications have appeared in Space Policy, Advances in Space Research, Environmental Ethics, Ethics & the Environment, Philosophia Mathematica, and in several volumes of Springer's Space and Society series.
    View full text